About
Content
Store
Forum

Rebirth of Reason
War
People
Archives
Objectivism

Post to this threadMark all messages in this thread as readMark all messages in this thread as unreadBack one pagePage 0Page 1


Post 20

Thursday, September 2, 2004 - 8:17amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit

“An object is monstrous where by its size it defeats the end that forms its concept.

The colossal is the mere presentation of a concept which is almost too

great for presentation, i.e., borders on the relatively monstrous; for

the end to be attained by the presentation of a concept is made harder

to realize by the intuition of the object being almost too great for

our faculty of apprehension. A pure judgement upon the sublime must,

however, have no end belonging to the object as its determining

ground, if it is to be aesthetic and not to be tainted with any

judgement of understanding or reason.”

Kant

 

“Now in the aesthetic estimate of such an immeasurable whole, the sublime

does not lie so much in the greatness of the number, as in the fact

that in our onward advance we always arrive at proportionately greater

units.”

Kant

 

O.K. there are a few things going on here in these two quotes:

1. A monstrous thing is so big that you cannot grasp it. Consequently Kant thinks this is sublime.

2. The colossal is not so big that it can be “taken-in” as a whole. Not particularly important to Kant.

3. A pure judgment must not identify a theme and show with reason its nature.

 

4. To be sublime the thing cannot not be grasped as a unit but as something infinite.

 

There are many contemporary postmodern works that embody these attributes. Christo’s Umbrellas is great example.

 

Christo, America's leading conceptual artist, raised and spent 26 million dollars on his Umbrellas, 1991 project.

http://home.earthlink.net/~kitathome/LunarLight/moonlight_gallery/images/1991-10-01-11_ChristoUm.jpg

 

Over 3,000 industrial-sized umbrellas were placed simultaneously over large tracts of land in California and Japan. These umbrellas extended beyond what your eye could see. So that from the vantage point of any one umbrella there was always one you couldn’t see. Intellectually, one could imagine that they stretched from California to Japan.

 

Clearly this is an example of something that cannot be grasped as a whole, you cannot take it in as one unit or as an end in itself.

 

Related to point three, not so much as our judging it but from what the piece is about, it doesn’t make any sense. It cost 26 million dollars, it really was a monumental project, and at the end of 18 days was completely dismantled as if nothing had existed. So for us it would be almost impossible to “taint” this piece with any “judgement of understanding or reason” simply because it is a monstrous act of anti-reason.

 

Another more recent piece is Rauschenberg’s ¼ Mile work, a series of lithographs, lined end on end to cover the distance of a quarter mile.

http://www3.nb.sympatico.ca/motion/images/luelrausch.gif

 

Composition for an artist is how the images, forms, colors, light, etc balance in the work as a whole. This is impossible to do with the Rauschenberg piece because he or us would never see the image as whole, this would then fall under Kant’s concept of the sublime and be superior to artists that make brilliant compositions.

 

If I were a postmodernist I could come up with all kinds of variations on this and other Kantian concepts of the sublime. For instance, a painting which folds in two would then have essentially two surfaces facing in opposite directions. You wouldn’t be able to see the painting as whole. Get the idea? Of course this would destroy the concept as composition of the painting as a whole.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

(Edited by Newberry on 9/02, 8:43am)


Post 21

Thursday, September 2, 2004 - 8:40amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Michelle: "Amazing how Kant was willing to abnagate his own genius, given how much effort was needed to write the Critique!"

On the other hand Michelle there might be a very good reason. Agatha Cristie was adamant that one should not "open your heart to evil." Kant could have opened his heart to evil and hence the significant importance for him, in relation to his concepts of the sublime, of not acknowledging the ends of things and and being so adamant that one should not use "understanding and reason" in one's judgment. Those ideas can only come about by someone who does not want to see.

More to come.

Michael


Post 22

Friday, September 3, 2004 - 10:07amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit

“For the sublime, in the strict sense of the word, cannot be

contained in any sensuous form, but rather concerns ideas of reason,

which, although no adequate presentation of them is possible, may be

excited and called into the mind by that very inadequacy itself

which does admit of sensuous presentation.”

Kant

 

By “sensuous form” Kant doesn’t mean a beautiful curve of a woman’s hip.  Now the concept of an object, so far as it contains at the same time the ground of the actuality of this object, is called its end, and the agreement of a thing with that constitution of things which is only possible according to ends, is called the finality of its form.”

 

Form is the whole work; painting, symphony, novel, sculpture, etc. The “sensuous” part is not about eroticism but about the communication of the form through the senses.

 

Kant was dead before Beethoven’s 9th, but he would/should have known about Bach, Mozart, Michelangelo, Rembrandt, Dante,…the artists’ works circulated as copies, etchings, etc. It is very difficult to understand how Kant could elevate something that “no adequate presentation of them is possible” over Don Giovanni or The Pieta. (Though envy as a possible motive would fit his adamant rejection of beauty as “repugnant” in favor of his concepts of the sublime which awaken “displeasure.”

 

Kant’s calling something aesthetically sublime with no referent to “sensuous form”, i.e. art, is an impossible break between the highest, grandest visions of artists with their means of presentation. He relegates “sensuous form” to merely a craft and conceptually dismisses great artists from greatness.  

 

BTW, in my late 20’s and early 30’s, many postmodern artists when they viewed my work told me, with a wink, what a great craftsman I was. I knew then that they were maliciously stating that I was an inferior artist because I painted integrated works and didn’t get the bigger, more enlightening picture, that great art wasn’t about expression through paint but was conceptual with a disturbing edge to it, i.e. the Kantian view of the sublime. They probably didn’t know anything about Kant, at least not with any depth, but these types of thoughts were/are rampant through the art world.

 

 

 


Post 23

Friday, September 3, 2004 - 11:25amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Michael,

First, I'd like to thank you for sifting through Kant's Critique and finding these illuminating quotes for the benefits of those who cannot bring themselves to read the entire Critique, like myself.

Kant's claim that the sublime is superior to the beautiful becuase it is abstract while the beautiful is "only" sensory is echoed in the early 20th century poem "The Statue" which I translated from Hebrew and is posted on Monadnock.net:

http://www.monadnock.net/translations/tchern_statue.html

The poet, Saul Tchernikhovski, was heavily influenced by Nietzsche. Still, he expresses *a conflict* over the fact that God remains an abstraction. Obviously, the problem is the choice of the subject: The Judeo-Christian God cannot be "reduced" to an image of marble, however beautiful. I think the sculptor in the poem represents the crossroad between representational and abstarct art. His successors chose the abstract. The poem also expresses Tchernikhovsky's own conflict as a Jew fascinated with Pagan Greece but unable to give up his religious belief. Sensory Zeus could not replace the sublime God of the Old Testament.

-- Michelle


Post 24

Friday, September 3, 2004 - 2:44pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit

Thanks Michelle for the including the link to the poem and the connections you make. Also for the acknowledgment.

 

The truth is I have lived so long in relationship to Kant's Critique it feels like a neurotic brother! and its easy for me to remember comments he made like the very relevant one below in relationship to what you have brought forth.

 

"We have no reason to fear that the feeling of the sublime will

suffer from an abstract mode of presentation like this, which is

altogether negative as to what is sensuous. For though the

imagination, no doubt, finds nothing beyond the sensible world to

which it can lay hold, still this thrusting aside of the sensible

barriers gives it a feeling of being unbounded; and that removal is

thus a presentation of the infinite. As such it can never be

anything more than a negative presentation-but still it expands the

soul. Perhaps there is no more sublime passage in the Jewish Law

than the commandment: "Thou shalt not make unto thee any graven image,

or any likeness of any thing that is in heaven or on earth, or under

the earth, etc." This commandment can alone explain the enthusiasm

which the Jewish people, in their moral period, felt for their

religion when comparing themselves with others, or the pride
inspired by Mohammedanism."
Kant

Kant is making clear again that the sublime is not associated with sensuous form, with art. The sublime is something that “expands the soul” and yet has the indefinable something of the “infinite” not to be found in any image or likeness.

 

One perspective on Kant’s critique that is very important is that he is constantly putting down the superlative power of art. If he were commenting on the sublimity of Ideas as such that could be understood, but he chooses to create a context in which his concepts of the sublime are juxtapose against art at every opportunity.





(Edited by Newberry on 9/03, 3:14pm)


Post 25

Saturday, September 4, 2004 - 2:45pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I just want to add that I recently read a book, Aesthetics and Art Theory: An Historical Introduction, by Harold Osborne.  Of Kant's aesthetic theory, he says: "This theory is the most important anticipation of the modern aesthetic outlook in any philosopher before the twentieth century."

In addition to his treatment of the sublime, I also see problems in his emphasis on true aesthetic appreciation as being radically "disinterested" and devoid of emotion.  This seems to strip sense-of-life reactions out of the realm of aesthetics, which is exactly wrong.


Sanction: 18, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 18, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 18, No Sanction: 0
Post 26

Sunday, September 12, 2004 - 8:56pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
My favorite quote from Kant's aesthetics is this, from section 49 of his Critique of Aesthetic Judgement:

"The imagination (as a productive faculty of cognition) is a powerful agent for creating, as it were a second nature out of the material supplied to it by actual nature. [Three sentences later...] Such representations of the imagination may be termed ideas. This is partly because they at least strain after something lying out beyond the confines of experience, and so seek to approximate to a presentation of rational concepts (i.e., intellectual ideas), thus giving to these concepts the semblance of an objective reality."

The similarity of this view of art to that of Ayn Rand and Suzanne Langer (and others) is striking. Langer's Feeling and Form (predating Rand's earliest aesthetics lectures by 5 years) is peppered with references to how art (of all different forms) presents a semblance (she prefers this term to "image," which she regards as too specifically visual) of a world. And Rand, of course, speaks of re-creation of reality which, Peikoff explains, refers to the creation of a "microcosm" (see OPAR).

As Gilbert and Kuhns note in their History of Esthetics (Dover), various Renaissance artists viewed art in the same way Kant did centuries later. They were concerned to create a "second nature," another world (albeit, one of the imagination). The noted Aristotelian aesthetician, Stephen Halliwell, traces this view back to Aristotle. So, there is a long and venerable trail of historical antecedents for Rand's concept of art.

Best to all,
Roger Bissell


Post 27

Monday, September 13, 2004 - 8:26amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit

Of course, Rand didn’t stop there. Holding a philosophy and a morality for living on earth, she explained that, in objectifying “ideas,” art enables man to hold the integrated total of his moral metaphysics as a beacon and searchlight in his consciousness in order to fulfill his deepest values. She forged a link between the nature of art and its function as a purifier of his awareness. She showed that art meets a need of man’s consciousness, which is his most important tool of survival.


Sanction: 18, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 18, No Sanction: 0
Sanction: 18, No Sanction: 0
Post 28

Wednesday, September 29, 2004 - 10:26pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
I have another favorite quote from Kant's Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. In section 45, he said, "Fine art is an art, so far as it has at the same time the appearance of nature." That is, fine art is not just a man-made object, but a man-made object that appears to be, as he said later in section 49, a "second nature," i.e., an imaginary microcosm of this world, a re-creation of reality.

Best 2 all,
Roger Bissell


Post 29

Thursday, September 30, 2004 - 10:43amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit

Hi Roger,

 

It’s a pleasure to see that you among other artists have read up on Kant. You are quite right in liking this comment and other comments made by Kant about art and beauty. Kant is very astute.

 

Earlier on in this thread I mentioned that Kant gave very good summations about the nature of art and beauty but that in the overall context he compares concepts of beauty unfavorably to, his aesthetic contribution, The Concepts of the Sublime.

 

There is, I believe, slight of hand going on here. He shows us how well he understands what art is and has been but that it is merely a craft and that the more serious and rigorous student seeking the furthest reaches of human states will bypass beauty for the sublime.

 

As I have been showing Kant’s concepts of the sublime are the antithesis of the concepts of the beauty.

 

I am sure you recall Toohey’s approach to squashing greatness: since he cannot stop Roark from becoming known, the next play was to elevate mediocrity to the status of genius thereby destroying the concept greatness/genius and consequently making it impossible for people to have a standard on which to judge.

 

Kant has done precisely this. Since great philosophers and artists have existed and expressed themselves irrefutably the next step is to acknowledge that and then create a superior standard, the Emperor has no clothes type of thing or, more viciously, The Concepts of the Sublime.

 

Kant’s genius gives truth to the concept that philosophy is like a blue print for a culture. His Concepts of the Sublime brilliantly anticipates today’s postmodern high art.

 

Michael

 

 


Post 30

Friday, October 1, 2004 - 7:47amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Michael,
Would you say that the following reflects the essence of Kant's emphasis of the sublime over the beautiful:

"Metaphysics -- the science that deals with the fundamental nature of reality -- involves man's widest abstractions. It includes such a vast sum of knowledge and such a long chain of concepts that no man could hold it all in the focus of his immediate conscious awareness. Yet he needs that sum and the awareness to guide him -- he needs the power to summon them into full conscious focus.

"That power is given to him by art."

J


Post 31

Friday, October 1, 2004 - 11:29amSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit
Incidentally, I think Kant's use of "disinterest" in relation to beauty is being misunderstood here. It's been a very long time since I've studied Kant's thoughts on aesthetics, but I don't think he was saying that we shouldn't have an interest in, or reverence for, beauty, but merely that we should ~define~ beauty with disinterest -- with dispassion or objectivity, without emotional predispositions or biases.

Also, Kant's mention of the "rage" of a forlorn hope isn't necessarily indicative of anger. Rage can mean intensity, fervor or ardor. To quote one of my favorite poems:

As time leads me further from precious past
I delay surrender to history's page
Splendor unfading, fidelity fast
In honor of passion's enduring rage.

Both "fast" and "rage" are often misunderstood in this stanza. "Fast" in this case means firmly fixed, not speedy. "Rage" means enthusiasm or fervor, not anger.

I don't think Kant's examples of the sublime were meant to negate beauty, but to indicate that dealing with the magnitude of the sublime is more essential than beauty is to the nature and purpose of art. I think he'd agree with Rand that beauty is a quality of art, but the essence of art is to help us get our minds around quantities -- "vast sums of knowledge" and "long chains of concepts" which "no man could hold in the focus of his immediate conscious awareness."

J

Post 32

Friday, October 1, 2004 - 3:05pmSanction this postReply
Bookmark
Link
Edit

Jonathan asks:
"Would you say that the following reflects the essence of Kant's emphasis of the sublime over the beautiful:

"Metaphysics -- the science that deals with the fundamental nature of reality -- involves man's widest abstractions. It includes such a vast sum of knowledge and such a long chain of concepts that no man could hold it all in the focus of his immediate conscious awareness. Yet he needs that sum and the awareness to guide him -- he needs the power to summon them into full conscious focus.""

 

No. Not at all. Rand's statement above would fit nicely in how Kant sees beauty: form, theme, end, connected to the senses; the total package.

 

By including the concept of the formless nature of the sublime Kant breaks with the above, irrevocably.

 

Representation depictions of color on a two-dimensional surface, painting, is a universal form that has been with us since the dawn of humanity, over 30,000 years and counting. The furthest reaches of painting, in actuality the sublime, the integration of spatial depth, form, light, and movement has been advanced by such artists as da Vinci, Rembrandt, and many other artists that have perhaps not integrated everything but have furthered particular aspects, like Monet's development of color/daylight or Bouguereau's realistic advancement of painting life-like flesh.

 

Kant's inclusion of the formless in his definition of the sublime wipes out the defining characteristic of art, such the medium of painting, so that the sublime is not about the medium or form but about thought only.

There is a very important point in understanding Kant's aesthetic thought, and which can only be gained by standing back and seeing how he juxtaposes sublime vs.beauty/art.

There is no good justification, in aesthetics, to replace art for thought.

 

 



Post to this threadBack one pagePage 0Page 1


User ID Password or create a free account.